Money is not content with being just another final purpose of life alongside wisdom and art, personal significance and strength, beauty and love; but in so far as money does adopt this position it gains the power to reduce the other purposes to the level of means. . . . To insist on keeping them as if they were incomparable values must appear stupid as long as one can get them back for money at any time, and above all as long as the precise expressibility of their monetary value has robbed them of their existing individual significance and their significance outside the purely indifferent economy.
Georg Simmel, The Philosophy of Money
In the orthodox rational choice model, risk aversion follows straightforwardly from diminishing marginal utility. If diminishing marginal utility holds over all goods, humans should be risk averse with respect to all goals. Nevertheless, this generalization has many apparent counterexamples, ranging from the trivial (e.g. gambling) to an importance so great that any theory of human action would be remiss to overlook it. In this latter category are those pursuits from which humans derive existential “meaning”, pursuits supported by an array of aphorisms (“nothing ventured, nothing gained”; “better to have loved and lost than never to have loved at all”) and moralizing tales of deathbed regrets.
In attempting to explain the difference between these existential pursuits and what may be called “ordinary” risk aversion, we may start from a stylized fact: risk aversion is observed to be strongest in pursuits with money at stake – hence its importance for economics. The effect is at least diminished with respect to the prospect of in-kind returns. Marwell & Ames (1981), for example, find that contributions to a public good fund are nearly twice as much (43% versus 84%) when the public good is indivisible than when it is simply a proportional monetary return. This is a counterintuitive result, considering non-fungibility of the indivisible good renders it less useful than cash.1 While it is true that money can itself be an existential pursuit for some, more often existential pursuits are objects – like the indivisible public good – with less easily quantifiable returns: games, career, artistry, or love, where the payoff is something like self-respect or the acclaim of one’s peers.
Money, of course, is subject to diminishing marginal returns, in an axiomatic sense. To the extent that money can be allocated from one use to another, an agent spends his first increment of income on his most urgently felt want (subjectively speaking), his second increment on his second most urgently felt want, and so on (cf. the argument in Mises [1966] p. 119ff).2 By this reasoning, the power to allocate a good is a sufficient condition for diminishing marginal utility – earlier increments will be allocated to more urgently felt wants. The observation of risk aversion with monetary stakes is, therefore, follows from the bare logic of choice: the use to which a lost hundred dollars would have been put is more urgent than the use to which an additional hundred dollars would have been put. Just how much more urgently determines the convexity of the utility function over the relevant range: fungibility may mean the marginal utility of income diminishes slowly, but diminish it must.
Existential pursuits, in contrast, can not be allocated to various uses; they are non-fungible and – we shall call them – ultimate ends. To the extent that they are threshold goods, they may even exhibit increasing marginal utility (IMU) over some range. If a certain quantity of respect is necessary to achieve a desired social status, the next increment of respect will be far more valuable than the previous, precisely because respect is not something I can allocate to more urgently felt wants first. In this case, risk-loving behavior is indicated: for a fair gamble over respect, the prospect of gain may more than outweigh the prospect of equivalent loss.
Naturally, existential pursuits could not retain their IMU character if they could be exchanged for money. 3 This would imply the ability to “trade off” things like respect for money (or other goods) in both directions; to allocate it to its most urgent uses first, just as with money. While this can be done to some extent, the opportunity is usually idiosyncratic; it certainly would make no sense to institute a market for genuine and heartfelt respect. Attempts to sell ultimate ends for money are typically regarded with moral disgust; note the emotional connotation of the word “betrayal”. Attempts to buy ultimate ends for money, on the other hand – where they are not also regarded with moral disgust – are often regarded with a measure of pity. Love and friendship, for example, are usually thought to be “cheapened” by being exchanged for money, regardless of the amount.
The argument from the logic of choice constitutes the “inside perspective” on ultimate ends. But why should such ends be valuable in the first place? A functionalist sort of “outside perspective” lies in the fact that risk-loving behavior in certain domains confers positive externalities – or, perhaps, to confer positive externalities is risk-loving behavior so far as its effectiveness depends on similar behavior from others. This is certainly the case in modern economies. Entrepreneurship is a risk-loving activity. The expected value is, for most enterprises, small or negative. Yet what market economy could do without them? Low time preference, likewise, is risky. Savings, in whatever form, can be confiscated, lost, or debased, or the saver could suddenly die before being able to enjoy them. But industrial society depends on a large stock of savings to be intermediated. And in general, excellence is a consumption good for most activities in wealthy societies: not only unnecessary for survival, but actually costly on net to indulge in. In existential pursuits, virtue must usually be its own reward.
Hayek (1988) put the problem this way:
These rules ‘are not derived from any utility or advantage which either the particular person or the public may reap from his enjoyment of any particular good‘. Men did not foresee the benefits of rules before adopting them, though some people gradually have become aware of what they owe to the whole system. (emphasis in original)
These internalized “rules” – what we have called ultimate ends – are not merely the side constraints we typically think of as the “rules of justice” undergirding a liberal polity. They include, importantly, the aspirational goals which impel men to take risks that benefit the community. Barnard (1938) argues that this is as true of the firm as of the polity, noting that “organizations endure in proportion to the breadth of the morality by which they are governed. This is only to say that foresight, long purposes, high ideals, are the basis for the persistence of cooperation.”
If we are to take preferences as given, that would be that. Risk-loving behavior – foresight, long purposes, and high ideals – is rational given these norms. But the norms themselves are not rationally justifiable, at least from the individual’s perspective. “Why should virtue be its own reward?” “Why should I respect my hard-working peer?” “What have high ideals ever done for me?” “If ability is mostly genetic, why try at all?” In short, the problem is: in expected value terms, many of the behaviors upon which social cooperation in an industrial and cosmopolitan society depends are individually “irrational”. Miller (1992), for example, demonstrates at length the impossibility of designing efficient organizational incentive structures that align the incentives of all parties without a “culture” to “fill in the gaps”. The extensive development literature on trust, as well, should make it clear that the harmony of interests we take for granted in Western economies is by no means the default state of mankind, even in the most favorable formal policy environment.
In order to do any work, aspirational norms must serve as ultimate ends, not subject to any further justification. For this reason, they are reinforced by the array of aphorisms and morality tales. Strive to be excellent. Provide for the future. Take care of your fellows. And just as importantly, praise those who succeed at these things, even if you cannot. Such aphorisms, especially those embodied in children’s stories, will be the most reliable indicator of a culture’s aspirational norms. Their internalization itself constitutes the increasing marginal utility observed in these domains, leading to the risk-loving behavior that keeps the world turning.
The logic of marginalist rational choice stipulates a difference between preference (the shape of the utility function) and choice (the maximizing point achieved on the function). Preference drives the logic; choice is the object of that logic. Internalized norms are preference phenomena – in particular, preferences exhibiting increasing marginal utility. To return to the first example, ∂²U/∂(Respect)² > 0. This is the feature of preferences that results in risk-loving choices.
Max Weber ([1905] 2001) argued that Capitalist society was characterized by ever-increasing rationalization, one aspect of which is the drive to articulate and justify the norms that constitute one’s ultimate ends. The purpose of articulation is to render an idea consciously manipulable. The articulation of a norm, therefore, is an attempt to make the utility function itself an object of choice.
In principle this is not so uncommon. To deliberately change one’s own preferences aptly characterizes the attempt to solve a time-inconsistency problem (say, quitting smoking) by the development of a habit or discipline. This must be done with some ultimate end in mind: the norm which values that end has not yet been actualized, but it has been internalized as an aspirational goal. If it had not, there would be no time-inconsistency problem at all: smoke away. In any case, any voluntary solution to a time-inconsistency problem must be driven by some preference exhibiting increasing marginal utility.
The rationalizing impulse is precisely opposite; an anti-habit. Increasing marginal utility cannot be rationally justified; the object must constitute an ultimate end. When this end is itself made subject to conscious choice, its character as an ultimate end is destroyed, and it becomes subject to ordinary decreasing marginal utility. When meaning, ambition, and acclaim, like money, become subject to diminishing marginal utility, the result is pauperism, alienation, anomie, and all the other ills which critics have ascribed to industrial society since its very inception.4
This suggests why risk aversion rears its head most strongly in the monetary domain. Monetary calculation is a phenomenon of rationalization, just the same as the ex post articulation and rational justification of norms: both bring into deliberative consciousness what was previously accepted tacitly and without deliberation. The mode of thought required for monetary calculation is much more deliberate and conscious than the rough and fuzzy heuristics applied to barter exchanges. This being the case, “ordinary” risk aversion has nothing to counterbalance it. Since money itself exhibits diminishing marginal utility, nothing which is ordinarily reckoned in money terms can exhibit the increasing marginal utility that constitutes an ultimate end. No doubt this encapsulates the unease behind the literature in moral philosophy concerned with the moral limits of markets (see Brennan & Jaworski 2015 for a survey). The extension of the money economy is at the same time the extension of risk-aversion.
Norms as objects of choice are subject to the logic of diminishing marginal utility and thus can never, on their own, overcome time inconsistency or free-rider problems. For these purposes, the absoluteness of such norms is as important as their content. In truth, such norms can never be more than practically absolute. There is usually some cost beyond which any man will abandon a norm. But even this realization serves to undercut its practical absoluteness. However much men may fail to live up to those norms when faced with the exigencies of life, a society which ceases to regard them as aspirational will find itself increasingly unable to sustain social cooperation without externally imposed direction and hierarchy. This, perhaps, is the main factor behind the rise of leftist ideology and the consequent rise of the welfare and regulatory state in the West. Erasmus has triumphed over Luther: not only is “ought” taken to imply “can”, but (note the popular antipathy toward abstinence-only sex education) there is hardly now a more well-accepted argument for “ought not” than to demonstrate “cannot”. Indeed, the modish “privilege” concept is a reaction to an observed “cannot” which attempts – not to assist the under-“privileged”, who may have internalized but have not achieved, but to deliberately obliterate the “ought” contained in aspirational norms.
To be fair, the rationalistic impulse has allowed us to jettison many harmful norms as well. This was the original foundation of Occidental ascendancy following the industrial revolution. However self-destructive the rationalistic impulse may be, it is not obviously worse than the alternative. The problem, as North (1990, p. 16) emphasizes, is that neither the unconscious evolution nor the rational reconstruction of social norms are subject to anything more than weak and distant feedback.5 There is little guarantee that a society’s aspirational norms confer positive, rather than negative, externalities on the community. Industrial society and the division of labor have certainly expanded the scope for human excellence and risk-loving behavior. But at the same time, the expansion of the money economy, as one instance of the increased rationalization of modern life, appears to undercut the justification for the sort of risk-loving behavior that was once lauded as virtue.
Buchanan’s “Natural and Artifactual Man” (1979) makes what can be read as a similar point. His concluding sentence, “man wants liberty to become the man he wants to become” can be read as a paean to the importance of self-direction as an aspirational norm.
Nevertheless, the structure of the argument is somewhat different. Buchanan lauds man’s capacity to choose his own goals, rather than choosing within the context of those goals. This, it might seem, is what I have argued exposes man to time-inconsistency problems and anomie.
Buchanan relates the lecture to his previous work on constitutional choice by likening the ‘artifactual’ act of choosing one’s own goals (as opposed to making choices consistent with given goals) to writing a personal constitution – i.e. writing the rules of the game, as opposed to playing the game. There is a close analogy between knowledge and choice here. As Popper (1979) notes, “Knowledge never begins from nothing, but always from some background knowledge—knowledge which at the moment is taken for granted—together with some difficulties, some problems.” In other words, we can question any particular piece of knowledge only from the perspective of some other knowledge which we take for granted. This cannot, of course, go on ad infinitum: Hayek’s (1952) point that the mind can never explain itself is due to the fact that, at some level, we will not be able to articulate the knowledge upon which we stand in order to question it.
Much the same is true of choice: we always choose within some framework of norms which we must take as given. If we step back and make those norms themselves objects of choice, we make that choice within still another set of norms which we hold as given. There is no terminus from which we can ultimately choose all our norms, as a metaphysical notion of free will might imply. The number of steps back we can take is limited by the articulability of the norms within which we choose: at some level (and this, perhaps, is the point of Stigler & Becker [1977], which Buchanan criticizes), the norms within which we choose cannot be made objects of choice: they are too ineffable.
The distinction between playing a game and drafting the rules of the game takes account of one level of choice. The important point is that drafting the rules is itself a game that takes place within a further (possibly unarticulated or inarticulable) set of rules. The act of personal constitution-writing that he describes takes place within a given framework of aspirational norms. If we follow Buchanan in talking about discrete levels of choice, we may say his personal constitution is one level up. Man chooses who he wants to become only by taking the wider society’s aspirational norms as given. The problems described earlier come when man attempts to step back two levels up, and subject those aspirational norms themselves to conscious choice. What further norms does he rely on then?
The constitutional framework, Buchanan rightly notes, is less an analytical framework than an attitude. It is itself an aspirational norm; a deliberate choice to stop the regress at one level and take the norms further back for granted (and commits to doing this, perhaps, by denying their existence or importance). In an ontological sense, however, a strict division between the constitutional level and the level of ordinary action obscures the point by suggesting that choice in the former happens from a god’s-eye view, or perhaps from behind a “veil of ignorance”. This is why the problem of desiring to quit smoking is better expressed as a time-inconsistency problem than a constitutional decision. Man is not assuming a norm-free vantage point from which he can “choose who he wants to become”. All we need to say is that his long-term interests and his short-term interests are in conflict. His long-term interests, of course, are informed by these aspirational norms. He can make choices consistent with his long-term interests to constrain his short-term interests, but he can only do this by taking for granted a given set of aspirational norms – in this case good health or self-respect.
If this were not so, on what basis would he prefer non-smoking to smoking? On what basis would he prefer anything to anything else? This is precisely the danger of anomie in demanding rational justification too many levels back: these aspirational norms cannot be rationally justified because the norms upon which they are founded are unarticulated, and possibly inarticulable. If they are to be rejected on this basis, man has disavowed his power to aspire, and even to prefer.
In an otherwise tendentious critique of utilitarianism near the end of The Ethics of Liberty, Murray Rothbard asks an interesting question: how could Mises, as a thoroughgoing utilitarian and wertfrei economist, display such moral fortitude in defense of liberalism?
One does not have to be a believer in natural rights to make sense of the question. If there is any discipline that exemplifies the impulse to rationalize and articulate what was tacit and unconscious, and to disregard anything not amenable to this treatment, it is economics. The thrust of marginalist logic is to tear down all categorical imperatives. Given enforcement costs, there is an optimal non-zero amount of crime in a society. Given a time-dated income stream, there is often an optimal non-zero amount of debt to take out. And given the disutility of labor, there is an optimal non-total amount of effort to devote to any particular pursuit.
Where money cannot be exchanged for everything, marginalism purports to apply to every action. Very rarely will a corner solution obtain where the answer is “all” or “none”. Thus, economics education might well be expected to finish the job that monetary calculation started, to wit, the corrosion of norms as ultimate ends.
Marwell & Ames again demonstrate exactly this. No variation on their experiment resulted in less than 40% contribution to the public goods fund except running it on first-year economics graduate students, who contributed only 20% of their tokens. They also note, regarding the follow-up questionnaire, that “more than one-third of the economists either refused to answer the question regarding what is fair, or gave very complex, uncodable responses.” Evidently the ordinary norms of fairness animating everyone else had been at least half eroded, and a number of subsequent papers have confirmed the general pattern.
Perhaps, however, the antidote also lies in economics. These norms have long been recognized in the field, but have been widely underappreciated until the relatively recent advent of New Institutionalism. It is true that marginal logic as such applies always and everywhere, regardless of institutional context. But without internalized norms – what are now being called “informal institutions” – there is no guarantee in a non-integral world that maximizing and marginal behavior will result in an extended order. Indeed, Roger Koppl (2003) for example, has reinterpreted maximizing behavior as a special case of rule-following behavior. Whether or not this formulation serves to make the point more clearly than the formulation of norms as domains of increasing marginal utility, the aspect of “human nature” which requires practically absolute rules and aspirations must not be overlooked. Horwitz (2000) makes clear what’s at stake, putting the matter in Buchananesque terms (though, of course, referring to a level further back than Buchanan himself did):
Human actors require constitutional constraints because we are epistemologically unable to generate social order in any other way.
A proper appreciation for the importance of institutions and norms as ultimate ends can, perhaps, reverse any moral decline conditioned by the study of economics. There are, indeed, things worth disciplining one’s self for, regardless of whether the benefits redound entirely to the self. Perfectionism, for example – even taking pride in one’s work – cannot be rationally justified. But where would the world be without the contribution of such “irrational” perfectionists? Where would economics be if the great economists had heeded their own advice and devoted an “optimal” amount of effort to their pursuits?
We do a disservice to economics students, both intellectually and morally, by presenting marginalism without institutionalism. “Optimal amounts of everything” is a powerful and necessary mode of thought. But if we as teachers of economics are to avoid deserving to be drowned with a millstone around our necks, it must not be presented without the importance of those ultimate ends, norms and institutions, both constraining and aspirational, that undergird social cooperation in the extended order.
can certainly lead to the weakening of restraints – moral and social – upon our baser impulses and thus to an increase in lawlessness or antisocial behavior. But even where it does not unleash our worst impulses, it can lead to the weakening of our best ones; that is, to the decline of idealism, commitment, and striving, and thus to listlessness and apathy or to a degraded concentration on narrow self-indulgence.
If there exist no incentive or selective mechanisms that make cooperation in large groups incentive-compatible under realistic circumstances, functional social institutions will require a divergence between subjective preferences and objective payoffs – a “noble lie”. This implies the existence of irreducible and irreconcilable “inside” and “outside” perspectives on social institutions; . . .
Social cooperation is the major thing to be explained in both sociobiology and economics. From the perspective of the former, most species never achieve it at all. From the perspective of the latter, most societies never get very far along compared to the advanced Western societies of the modern world. One . . .
If the basic purpose of moral norms is to coordinate on the conditions under which one should cooperate in social dilemmas, this paper shows that the boundaries of such conditions must be fractal. In other words, as one focuses on the border of the area in signal space where the . . .
Leave a Reply